Received: from mail-pa0-f59.google.com ([209.85.220.59]:34377) by stodi.digitalkingdom.org with esmtps (TLSv1.2:ECDHE-RSA-AES128-GCM-SHA256:128) (Exim 4.86) (envelope-from ) id 1btgz9-0005V3-PU for lojban-list-archive@lojban.org; Mon, 10 Oct 2016 13:15:47 -0700 Received: by mail-pa0-f59.google.com with SMTP id hh10sf286202pac.1 for ; Mon, 10 Oct 2016 13:15:43 -0700 (PDT) DKIM-Signature: v=1; a=rsa-sha256; c=relaxed/relaxed; d=googlegroups.com; s=20120806; h=sender:subject:to:references:from:message-id:date:user-agent :mime-version:in-reply-to:content-transfer-encoding :x-original-sender:x-original-authentication-results:reply-to :precedence:mailing-list:list-id:x-spam-checked-in-group:list-post :list-help:list-archive:list-subscribe:list-unsubscribe; bh=eLr4p/leHY2CZwZ/S0EV6eFSrkXC+plANVFeAF4iBuA=; b=jEBGrAt4nAmSnhVd2jnr4KQmAuEy71Pavi2+Z6JHbACO4nQ1sJ0621DCy/Y3UwObCi 0hpKOjpanN1gpmkMUev12DkrOKqF7iWtl7bnohyZlTJabH1s8RQE4/TWVvXzoWzaIR18 ROdkYCpo55IFPM21Z1HWEsuCsDQq+vYbWTE30zJDNOnugDmyZSMSNx+VzjdNZWCriWye pkEIUwHkU+0TnxsnL/iXzTyLNqBdO/G2g4WfneF0CusQAwyhy6QDU96J0iybpugAlwGM w9Y4emFJuzA4i3sAoTYHbgVDlFoNuIOJFqa3cCKY09G1/MVaR5r9JNke/1qo0hcpFuac kMiQ== X-Google-DKIM-Signature: v=1; a=rsa-sha256; c=relaxed/relaxed; d=1e100.net; s=20130820; h=sender:x-gm-message-state:subject:to:references:from:message-id :date:user-agent:mime-version:in-reply-to:content-transfer-encoding :x-original-sender:x-original-authentication-results:reply-to :precedence:mailing-list:list-id:x-spam-checked-in-group:list-post :list-help:list-archive:list-subscribe:list-unsubscribe; bh=eLr4p/leHY2CZwZ/S0EV6eFSrkXC+plANVFeAF4iBuA=; b=lPhk5l/CcUm0lzD1dixt+t9Sz/euoCHh9rmmvOMBSmw3Xb/gWa5SB8QdYoMVu3ur+M E7c9Hpc3fxNmZi9aptB2U+hqIsXgBHWLgJKrMhe+7V8NHH6m/0mg+xC4eCL5yVJWiYnU XZUdvqsU1orqpgvTB9RG9Qkq1Ro2BTK88mCgPjzV4Il9TGdFexzHF6u68y8SMKaQTHvr jlu4utTLToUhCVtHgV3pa0SQ6GuONmb7n/tMdNIVi/+1K1aa10+KA5mSklM3zGIPbW8A lfzlxVaNrPDJQwAGfRX2hH0oWzyaal4DNdAX7GaJoLxNgXmPl+oNorcvvyh24GaM5F3u Mrhg== Sender: lojban@googlegroups.com X-Gm-Message-State: AA6/9RlKI9vOIypyy3KzLmBmXvx1HCmboUvY+UqoeJhXnye4lZhi4hQdpaBzqxHKReJe/Q== X-Received: by 10.157.55.181 with SMTP id x50mr2796otb.7.1476130537816; Mon, 10 Oct 2016 13:15:37 -0700 (PDT) X-BeenThere: lojban@googlegroups.com Received: by 10.157.39.117 with SMTP id r108ls21187ota.19.gmail; Mon, 10 Oct 2016 13:15:37 -0700 (PDT) X-Received: by 10.31.237.65 with SMTP id l62mr21648vkh.6.1476130537379; Mon, 10 Oct 2016 13:15:37 -0700 (PDT) Received: from mout.gmx.net (mout.gmx.net. [212.227.17.20]) by gmr-mx.google.com with ESMTPS id p70si1353558vkd.0.2016.10.10.13.15.37 for (version=TLS1_2 cipher=ECDHE-RSA-AES128-GCM-SHA256 bits=128/128); Mon, 10 Oct 2016 13:15:37 -0700 (PDT) Received-SPF: pass (google.com: domain of seladwa@gmx.de designates 212.227.17.20 as permitted sender) client-ip=212.227.17.20; Received: from [127.0.0.1] ([217.246.160.90]) by mail.gmx.com (mrgmx101) with ESMTPSA (Nemesis) id 0LtmK9-1aug0506uz-011A4u for ; Mon, 10 Oct 2016 22:15:36 +0200 Subject: Re: [lojban] A Simpler Quantifier Logic (blog article) To: lojban@googlegroups.com References: <3cb1fc04-c3d0-3535-099e-30b8b120f219@gmx.de> <99931644-56cd-b50f-401d-af57df7e64b0@gmx.de> From: selpahi Message-ID: <56f30b98-4848-32c1-b7e4-510f7be6434b@gmx.de> Date: Mon, 10 Oct 2016 22:15:58 +0200 User-Agent: Mozilla/5.0 (Windows NT 10.0; WOW64; rv:45.0) Gecko/20100101 Thunderbird/45.4.0 MIME-Version: 1.0 In-Reply-To: Content-Type: text/plain; charset=UTF-8; format=flowed Content-Transfer-Encoding: quoted-printable X-Antivirus: avast! (VPS 161010-3, 10.10.2016), Outbound message X-Antivirus-Status: Clean X-Provags-ID: V03:K0:DwwCdPpYoSclh2oEX8USZ20f7XC32pkdM0GbFyz7Z05iz/xmiDV gWxOsOyQjPVnZ+PeyPqtBbPz6yJaEHkFxTzfL5Wtf/Z8M07IDL+MIvzFtw9zW9HvsAAwCBx R3NjA1xfSzwC6kIEmZF7rl5Vz9/Hlz9dsrWO958ze6HZoFWUYaucJ4BscA1rdn8/WTpxO4w ovw/ZDGOowWL29j/d3NlQ== X-UI-Out-Filterresults: notjunk:1;V01:K0:Ar2CAGTk8bI=:8vlB7SFLsaAIQABracDygt LiCt9ZFDI7FWFriF15iK+oPNCKXLtOthUZJhnIjZiGG8zqrK/1pnp3AOKtERRuXW+O+Yerm9I Z+wafjtztzxUNUIr2U2nc6D79+p9GKBsB0U3tzaOWLA46mWhxBm3TRDD55OUeI7kb75SRB4nv QySfiKfbKkyjRgk5Pf61YrQ+w4kYGCJItamUhHoaXWv0kqamIwcOG51Y+vZhbyVKtmT6Vyz8c j9LsX/mzj3xyprlNOl9atJojS7EH02tZj0oY5//17ZN45EhHm0de3HE3cQFC41lH0SXgOsL5U 5uCU3KDvF11bN0ePiz9EUwMQJMpbRf5wCH01UgcAeE9nOZ05QAIhn6APLhh09bXrg1VABFPKN KDA5/6LwNl/168wWx0+DAd0PVCArsab/3fMKWMpt6h8EDojSos4Gzq+NK4hP6EGXB6c3k7SzM YMGvOwGozlw64Gyc8rKOxfXC19zUZpDOkCBhkhJTx666KWo5r+UX7Ae14gdrCPo9pYHtYsK2k qkSCi0nbmRPfpZwLx2LMVIDBfM2/A2F7COcrio8jjfyvri0gUlyhWlTV46IRuPYU8YgTuud2r ezAsHFFWSnhoOPa09pQWSTHD0O17YfbZ7uee8e+/lqLD6ob1o+PDNISGcTx6gzDvA9v27MsXX E5Ym1+S3qI7/XhPHQzJnDISu77nA29JWvrrh39vPlJuTAEMFcvWC1Os8VunfL36F0+APFTtkg 1QuQJufjQDtvZHzz/5Go3qlzs42xure1n7orKQDGS3C3xgJ571laUavfDxN3aVe8FR3dy5OBV FoE0G52 X-Original-Sender: seladwa@gmx.de X-Original-Authentication-Results: gmr-mx.google.com; spf=pass (google.com: domain of seladwa@gmx.de designates 212.227.17.20 as permitted sender) smtp.mailfrom=seladwa@gmx.de Reply-To: lojban@googlegroups.com Precedence: list Mailing-list: list lojban@googlegroups.com; contact lojban+owners@googlegroups.com List-ID: X-Spam-Checked-In-Group: lojban@googlegroups.com X-Google-Group-Id: 1004133512417 List-Post: , List-Help: , List-Archive: , List-Unsubscribe: , X-Spam-Score: -1.7 (-) X-Spam_score: -1.7 X-Spam_score_int: -16 X-Spam_bar: - On 10.10.2016 02:36, Jorge Llamb=C3=ADas wrote: > I don't believe a distributive "citka" is all that useful. I want to be > able to say "the children ate the whole cake" without having to > introduce any roundabouts. Of course. But I believe that a distributive {citka} does not prohibit this= . > It's also a simplification to say that there are only two kinds of > distributivity (fully distributive and fully collective). Those are just > the two extremes. Yes. I'm not saying there are only two kinds of distributivity (I will=20 go into more detail below), but I'm saying that it's possible to group=20 predicates into one of only two categories and deal with intermediate=20 distributivity via other means. > Unspecified distributivity in an argument place is a form of > ambiguity at the definitional level of a predicate. > > > No, it's just a form of vagueness, where you don't specify what you > don't want or need to specify. Let us look at some of the many possible meanings of a simple quantified=20 statement in English, say, "At least three people carried a chair": 1) At least three people are such that each of them carried a chair. 2) At least three people are such that each of them was involved in=20 carrying a chair. 3) Some people that are at least three moved a piano together. Would you say that all of these describe the same relationship or=20 different relationships? Or your "eating cake" example, would you say that each different reading=20 is a different meaning of "eat"? The way I see it, each reading has at its core the same base predicate,=20 "x1 eats x2", which is a simple relation of one thing eating another=20 thing. Everything else is built on top of this basic meaning, but the=20 meaning of {citka} itself does not change in the process. On the other hand, if you say {citka} means all sorts of things from the=20 get-go, then you start with ambiguity (or call it vagueness) and then=20 build additional vagueness on top as you create full statements. (Please=20 don't understand me as trying to get rid of fuzziness; no matter how=20 precise a definition is, there is always fuzziness, and there is nothing=20 wrong with that.) I mentioned above that there are other means by which intermediate=20 distributivity can be achieved, and by which "the children ate the cake"=20 is acceptable even with a distributive "eat". One such approach is one that we use in other areas of Lojban (or any=20 language) as well, and that is the idea of pragmatic slack. In certain=20 contexts and situations, sentences that are false when taken literally=20 can still be considered true at the level of detail that is currently=20 relevant. We don't care if really every single one of the things ate=20 cake, because it isn't relevant to our specific situation. Similarly, we=20 don't mind if someone says "I woke up at nine" when really they woke up=20 a few minutes after nine. Nevertheless, the meaning of "wake up at nine"=20 is not changed, nor is the meaning of "ate cake" changed. (Lasersohn (1999) discusses this in great detail) Another approach is to use the concept of a "cover" to account for=20 intermediate distributivity. A cover of a set is a set of subsets such=20 that each element of the original set is included in at least one of the=20 subsets. When a distributive claim is made, this is done via a universal=20 quantifier (which we do implicitly when the predicate place is=20 distributive), but instead of applying to 'all of the things', it only=20 quantifies universally over those of the things that are part of the=20 cover. The cover allows for certain individuals to drop out of the=20 picture. The predicate remains distributive with this approach, too. (Schwarzschild (1996) and Brisson (1998) use this approach) And additionally, when it is important, words like {kansi'u} exist (and=20 I have proposed that a bunch of similar words could exist that express=20 related forms of "doing something together", depending on the nature of=20 the togetherness (e.g. just being in the same place as some of them eat,=20 helping each other so that some of them eat, and so on). These are not=20 necessarily roundabout, and you would only use them when you think it=20 matters. So all in all, you may say it doesn't matter which approach we use as=20 long as you > can say "the children took the chairs to the garden" when you don't=20 know or don't care about how the action was distributed among children=20 and chairs. But it makes a difference to me, because in one case we throw our hands=20 in the air about the meaning of a predicate, and in the other case we=20 can decide what it means on a fundamental level. > There are other ways (for example, in the realm of pragmatics) to > deal with vague distributivity, outside of the definition of > argument places, and I prefer those ways. > > > I'm not too sure how stringent you want to be with defining > distributivity into all predicate places. For some places it's > reasonable that it be part of the definition of the predicate ("pavmei" > might be an example). {pavmei} cannot be distributive. It is only true of things that are one=20 in number. {[su'oi] re da pavmei} is false. If you meant its=20 distributivity type must be non-distributive, then yes. There are many predicates that only make sense non-distributively. There are also many predicates that are fundamentally distributive, and=20 where making them non-distributive only adds vagueness. > For other predicates, I don't see how forcing a > fixed distributivity helps, since there are things that can just as well > be done separately or together. It helps pin down the fundamental meaning of a predicate. But it makes me wonder. Is it really such a crazy idea for Lojban to=20 have different words for rather different kinds of carrying even though=20 English only has one? Let's not forget that Lojban is also a way to=20 experience new ways of thinking about situations. We split English words=20 into multiple distinct brivla all the time, why shouldn't we here? It=20 would be interesting. ~~~mi'e la solpa'i --- Diese E-Mail wurde von Avast Antivirus-Software auf Viren gepr=C3=BCft. https://www.avast.com/antivirus --=20 You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "= lojban" group. To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an e= mail to lojban+unsubscribe@googlegroups.com. To post to this group, send email to lojban@googlegroups.com. Visit this group at https://groups.google.com/group/lojban. For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/d/optout.