Return-Path: Resent-From: cbmvax!uunet!PICA.ARMY.MIL!protin Resent-Message-Id: <9107092025.AA07231@relay1.UU.NET> 16 Jun 90 14:15 EDT From: cbmvax!uunet!math.ucla.edu!jimc Return-Path: Message-Id: <9006140014.AA01642@julia.math.ucla.edu> To: snark!lojban-list Subject: Comments on Negation (longer :-( Date: Wed, 13 Jun 90 17:14:31 -0700 Resent-Date: Tue, 9 Jul 91 16:23:57 EDT Resent-To: John Cowan Status: RO X-From-Space-Date: Tue Jul 9 16:57:46 1991 X-From-Space-Address: cbmvax!uunet!PICA.ARMY.MIL!protin The negation paper is very complete, and there are several features discussed in it that I will want to add to -gua!spi. Most of my comments are not show-stoppers, but problems with various interpretations. 1. Scales The distinction made in the paper between "contradictory negation" and "selbri negation" is very important. Most (all?) selbri can be interpreted as specifying a scale, but only for a few gismu are there matching gismu for opposite scale ends (e.g. light/dark, happy/sad). The "polar opposite" cmavo is very useful to build new meanings, which should be interpreted as an affirmation of the opposite relation, rather than as a (logical) negation. One useful feature in -gua!spi that I didn't see in the paper was a "central opposite" cmavo which produces the neutral point on the scale. For example, the centralization of any color scale would be gray; "happy" would to to "bored" rather than "sad", and so on. I have found it useful to apply it also to central properties so that the central opposite of "level" is "tilted", "fresh" becomes "spoiled", and so on. ("Fresh" being defined as "undamaged by age or use", it is clearly the neutral point of an unsigned scale rather than the end of a signed scale. Unsigned scales are less common than signed scales. This one has "rotten" for its periphery.) In indicators I would be happer to see the prefix, tight-binding na'e of selbri negation rather than the trailing nai which is used in logical connectives as a logical (contradictory) word. Also, you would have to count words in actual text, but I'll bet you find that na'e (selbri negation) is a lot more common than na (contradictory). That's true in -gua!spi. And that's a motivation to exchange the words: two (English) syllables for one. As for grammar, I had good luck in Nalgol by sticking the selbri negator in the same grameme with conversions, since it binds similarly and occupies the same sites. A selbri-negated or converted modal operator is allowed, isn't it? You get neat meanings this way, interpreting them as abbreviations for a subordinate clause with the selbri equally converted or negated. As a matter of fact, why not let the indicator intensity cmavo apply to any selbri (I prefer the prefix position) to get the scale center? In other words, merge the indicator and selbri syntax, and interpret an indicator as an abbreviation for a subordinate clause with its selbri equally negated and intensified. 2. Negation of sumti I'm not too comfortable with using na, a raw contradictory negation, with an argument (sumti) predicate (selbri). Here's how I interpret an argument; see how close it comes to current Lojban doctrine. Identify the first case after conversion of the selbri, and stick a placeholder there. The selbri is the symbol for a relation, that is, a set of lists of case occupants. When there are sub-arguments (including modal), retain only members which have a referent of those subarguments in the right cases. Now make up a set from the case occupants of the placeholder case. This is the full referent set of the argument. Pick a subset according to the article, and those are the referents of the sumti. For example, try "eater of cheese". The placeholder goes in X1 (if in X2 the referents would be "foods"). The relation "eat" is here enumerated: X1 X2 1. The rat My cookies 2. The rat My cheese 3. Me My cheese 4. My kid An apple etc. Due to the sub-argument, members 1,4 are thrown out and 2,3 remain (plus possibly some others among the etc.) Now the case occupants over the placeholder are "the rat" and "me", and this set is the full referent set of the sumti -- what would be passed through if the article were "all". Now what is a "non-eater of cheese"? We've decided that selbri negation isn't right. The correct interpretation involves some kind of complementation -- either those X1's who eat other than cheese (i.e. all members of the "eat" referent set other than lines 2,3), or the complement (relative to some universe of discourse) of {"the rat", "me"}. I incline toward the second choice since had the first been wanted, the complementation operator would have been put on "cheese". Clearly if the referent set of a sumti is a set, the referent set of its negation must be derived by complementation. But I'm not able to say authoritatively what the universe of discourse should be. 3. Existential failure and bogus assertions of existence I learned (after much agony) that an assertion about all the members of the null set is true. St. Anselm's Ontological Proof of the Existence of God is the most famous example. Here's a more mundane one. Let "the king" mean "the current king of France" which, as a set, is void. "All cats have hair" may or may not be true. Each of the following propositions is equivalent to each other: (The king has hair) and (all cats have hair) - --Union of arguments in extension-- (The king -union- all cats) have hair - --Compare argument to "all cats"-- All cats have hair (For all Q: (P and Q) = Q) implies (P = .TRUE.) Thus (generalizing outrageously over the involved predicate), "the king has hair" is proven true. QED. (Also, "the king is bald" is true.) The footnote (6) that use of "lo" constitutes some kind of assertion that something exists: I don't see how this can be. I see this interpretation instead: "lo nolraitru" is a sumti with a referent set. "Lo" means (among other things) that referents must fit the selbri, and the quantity of such referents turns out to be zero. Thus an assertion is made about the members of the null set, but I don't see any assertion about whether any king of France exists. To make such, you would have to put on a subordinate clause (assertion type, not restriction) with a numeric predicate, stating that more than zero members were present. (By the way, I find it very useful to quantify with zero to make a negative statement, as you mention.) As to what quantifiers mean: My feeling is that before the article (no lo nolraitru) it means to take a subset with that count, selection in-mind. After the article (lo no nolraitru) it's a "subordinate comment": not restrictive, but not exactly a real assertion either. It's there to help the listener identify the referents (in this case by clarifing the count). If the referents fail to match the comment the speaker has been unhelpful, but has not made an assertion that can be denied, particularly with "le" (in-mind selection). Subordinate comments have turned out to be quite important in -gua!spi, and are about equally common as restrictive clauses and subordinate assertions. 4. Explicit scales The machinery for explicitly specifying a scale is good to have. I shall have to make sure that -gua!spi expresses scales efficiently. The concept reminds me of how dimensioned quantitites are specified: you assert that an argument is on the scale (i.e. "I am heavy") and then put on a restrictive subordinate clause asserting that the main bridi is a member of an equivalence class of things with a particular measure ("70 kilos"). I believe this model works equally well for non- numeric dimensions: "The chair is colored" restricted by "main bridi is in the `red' equivalence class of colored events". The problem is that we are used to saying "the chair is red" and implying the scale; I'm not sure if that's viable under the scale/restriction model, and if not, whether it's then unreasonable to demand that the scale/restriction model be used. 5. Negation of Bizarre Gramemes I think logically connected abstractions are ridiculous. This is better: One abstraction word "nu" means "X1 is an event in the referent set of the following relation (bridi)". For "degree/quantity" you have (already) a gismu whose X2 is an abstraction, and similarly for "property", and an identity transformation for "event". You use internal selbri conjunction (on a shared X2 argument) for your abstraction conjunctions, and similarly for negation. It's ridiculous to try to make ellipsis possible in every corner of the grammar; you have to use selbri as the foundation of meaning, and then make various efficiency hacks that are interpreted as abbreviations of clauses. Then the wierd and wonderful concepts like connected or negated abstractions are easily handled at the selbri level, outside the grammar, and not only that, arbitrary extensions to the category (here, abstractions) are possible without grammar hacks; the speakers just use existing gismu creatively in the clause form. 6. go'i Go'i (previous sentence anaphor): I agree with your analysis that all material (specifically negation) on go'i replaces matching material in the antecedent, or supplements if no match. The final sentence (section 15) brings up a problem: just what is the antecedent of go'i? In -gua!spi I define it as the previous sentence said by the current listener, which seems to be the sense used here. Also, when a connected sentence is the antecedent what do you do? (Cry!) James F. Carter (213) 825-2897 UCLA-Mathnet; 6221 MSA; 405 Hilgard Ave.; Los Angeles, CA, USA 90024-1555 Internet: jimc@math.ucla.edu BITNET: jimc%math.ucla.edu@INTERBIT UUCP:...!{ucsd,ames,ncar,gatech,purdue,rutgers,decvax,uunet}!math.ucla.edu!jimc