Return-Path: <@FINHUTC.HUT.FI:LOJBAN@CUVMB.BITNET> Received: from FINHUTC.hut.fi by xiron.pc.helsinki.fi with smtp (Linux Smail3.1.28.1 #1) id m0rBjij-00007EC; Sun, 27 Nov 94 15:32 EET Message-Id: Received: from FINHUTC.HUT.FI by FINHUTC.hut.fi (IBM VM SMTP V2R2) with BSMTP id 1739; Sun, 27 Nov 94 15:32:57 EET Received: from SEARN.SUNET.SE (NJE origin MAILER@SEARN) by FINHUTC.HUT.FI (LMail V1.1d/1.7f) with BSMTP id 1737; Sun, 27 Nov 1994 14:49:54 +0200 Received: from SEARN.SUNET.SE (NJE origin LISTSERV@SEARN) by SEARN.SUNET.SE (LMail V1.2a/1.8a) with BSMTP id 4186; Sat, 26 Nov 1994 23:22:08 +0100 Date: Sat, 26 Nov 1994 14:23:35 -0800 Reply-To: "John E. Clifford" Sender: Lojban list From: "John E. Clifford" Subject: Ol Uncle Tom Cobleigh X-To: lojban list To: Veijo Vilva Content-Length: 13236 Lines: 194 I used imperatives to make a point in the "any" thread of the current tangle, then carelessly picked it up thinking it was in the "opaque" thread. Thank you, Xorxes, for setting me straight. Imperatives, however odd they may be in other respects, are not opaque: identity substitutions preserve satisfaction and quantifying in presents no problems (unless, of course, the command takes one into an opaque context, "Don't think about the Wizard of Oz" -- the person, not the book). Pulling quantifiers out does not work in general, but that is not so much opacity as the problems of when and who gets to make choices. The point of the example, that some references in opaque contexts work outside, remains, though. Sorry if I caused any confusion (more than usual for me). I take my job here to proclaim the orthodoxy of formal logic, to apply it to Lojban when possible and to defend it when necessary. Happily, logical orthodoxy is as Episcopalian as I am (or as "big-tent" Republican as I am not), embracing or at least tolerating a variety of points of view over a broad spectrum of questions, tied together by a commitment to a few basic practices. One of the realms of (usually) friendly disagreement is about the range of the quantifiers. The extreme positions here are that bound variable range only over actually existing things in this world (the extreme extreme would not even allow numbers and suchlike mathematical entities) and that they range over the existents of all possible worlds (and maybe even impossible ones). Lojban has officially (I think) taken the view that quantifiers in a world range over the things that exist (zaste) in that world. McCawley* reminds us that ordinary languages are more generous than that, though less than a rabid substitutionalist would allow, and Lojban practice has tended to follow natural language practice when no one hauls it back into line with theory. As McCawley notes, we tend to allow the characters of established fiction and even those loosely related to them -- Ulysses and Sherlock Holmes and Data and even Sherlock's mistress and my son are all in (having a name is a sufficient condition in almost all of the expansionist logical views) and even, occasionally, unnamed members of classes from such tales (unicorns, for example, none of which has a name -- that I know of, anyhow). We say such paradoxical things (for a strict constructionist) as "There are mythical beasts" which we then instantiate, when challenged, with "Unicorns". And we surely allow that, if both Rembrandt and Picasso drew pictures of Zeus, that there is something (even someone) that they both drew pictures of -- even if they illustrated different events in the tales, so the quantification is not over events in which Zeus appears. And, of course, we quantify -- in English often but constantly in Lojban -- over events that never obtain. (I personally have no objection to saying that events exist even if they never obtain, but even some expansionists are not so liberal.) Even if we allow a richer range for variables than just the real existents, we still need to bring our focus back to them from time to time: for science if nowhere else but for many practical matters as well. The laws of physics nor aerodynamics need not account for flying carpets nor is even the reformed Scrooge a source for a loan. And many predicates require that their various arguments have the same ontic status: we can only hit what is in the world with us, for example. We could, within an expanded quantifier range, always haul back to the real with an appropriate predicate, _zaste_ in Lojban, "real" or "exist" in English. But in a logical language, it is often more convenient to use a different quantifier for the two cases. And right now we seem to have two quantifier sets floating around, one of which is already being used (pretty much unofficially) for what bes and the other for what exists -- except that the two concepts are not separated consistently. Using _da_ alone and with _poi_ (for predicates non-empty in this world) for the strong quantifier ("there exists") and _lo_ for the weak ("there is" or "bes") would solve a number of current controversies and a few old ones and head off a few that have been long abrewing but have not yet -- or only just now -- come on the scene: the problem with event descriptions as needed for intensional predicates, for example. I recommend that we change the official line accordingly. All of which has almost NOTHING to do with opacity. What it does have to do with opacity is that it suggests a principle for determining what terms are imported from outside into an opaque context and, consequently, can be picked up by external (weak) quantifiers. We could consider a range of answers, but the most likely one in practice is one a little to the right of what counts as being in this world, probably a name or a clear association with something whose being in the world is not in doubt. The safest cases -- after those explicitly mentioned in the surrounding non-opaque context-- are all the _le_ descriptions (picked out by the clearly real speaker), deictic and possessed descriptions (_lovi_ and _lodo_, etc. -- again because of their association with real persons and places in the world) and proper names. But we can adjust from this base as needs be. Whether we want to let in the established classes of nameless (unicorns, elves) or not or restrict the names to established ones in some way, for example, are points usage will decide -- as it has already voted, more or less clearly, for some such expansion. Notice that binding on the outside does not affect the other properties that define an opaque context. External identities need not apply: Hesperus, Phosphorus and Venus can be quite different things in the intensional realm and George Bush and the President of the United States can be the same. Nor does this allow fronting quantifiers -- even weak ones -- from the opaque contexts to the outside: even if we confine our list of possible suspects to externally identified people, the fact that I know someone killed the Viscount does not mean that there is someone I know to have killed the Viscount. But still this move may have some practical consequences for Lojban usage, again bringing theory into conformity with practice. As I have noted, sumti from opaque context need to be marked when the context is not apparent (sumti-raising, generally) and externally established terms in opaque contexts also could use a mark, at least optionally, when generalizing was in the offing. And, as Xorxes keeps insisting, for some terms, we want to just use them alone in reduced opaque contexts. So, with established terms we might allow that the raising marker from its current use and the external establishment marker from the opaque context cancel each other out, leaving just the bare term (with some danger in other respects, but probably minor). So we could say _mi_sisku_lemi_cukta_. That does imply that all of the opaque-making terms have been brought together into a common format. As I have said, I think that that format should be one requiring an event description in the place. Objects then come in as raised sumti from such descriptions. The objections to this proposal seem to be that it leaves vague descriptions when the object only appears, that it does not fits some cases -- representations and _sisku_, and that some event descriptions are not opaque -- "I saw someone playing pool," for example. To the vagueness case, it seems to me sufficient to point out that the notion wanted is already vague: "I need a box" does not say what I need the box for nor does it say in what relation I need to stand to the box: possession? use of? will bare existence and propinquity do? It depends on what I need the box for, probably, and if it does, we can figure it out in Lojban as well as we can in English. And Lojban even has a way of saying "a vague event involving _lo_tanxe_". On the other side, I would argue that all the representations are not merely representations of some object but of that object in context, doing something, being something, i.e., as satisfying some predicate and so in an event. We never get a picture of Zeus plain , for example, but only of him reigning or raping or.... Of course, there are painting that don't represent anything, but then the raising problem hardly arises. As for _sisku_ (and its presumed ilk, though no one ever offers another one), I suggest they have absorbed their event description into their own deep structure -- moving it from syntax to semantics -- so that, although they only take object sumti, those object sumti are to be marked as raised nonetheless. As for my person seen playing pool, I still do not believe that this is an event description, even though I am still unsure of how to represent it adequately. Short notes: Opaque contexts screw up connectives as well as quantifiers. "I want coffee or tea" need not entail "I want coffee or I want tea", I may be undecided between the two (and another's report of my state of mind will be equally indecisive). Lojban has several different constructions for the English and at least some of them make the failure of the inference apparent (sorry I can't lex them. Is there a current cmavo list somewhere in the bowels of Yale? My list lacks many used a lot here and seems to be wrong about some it does have, to the point that I do not trust it.) Fiction is opaque because real identities cannot necessarily be exchanged within it: Hesperus and Venus, for example. But it is global and so may have its own opacities -- and indeed its own fictions (The Ocean of Stories or the Thousand and One Nights) -- within it. And of course, quantifiers do not work and weak ones need some help (but the story itself may be justification enough). Chassell's suggestion to think subjunctively does not help me understand or verify a sentence which means different things depending on whether it is true or false. Subjunctive reasoning gives hypothetical conclusions and I want to know what the sentence means and/or whether it is true. Suppose I reason that if the sentence is true than it means that situation s obtains but situation s does not obtain. So, if the sentence were true, it would be false since it describes the world as it is not. Thus, the sentence is false. If it is false it means that situation z obtains -- and, since it is false, situation z ought not obtain. But what if situation z does obtain. The sentence is then true, if it means what it means when it is false, but it is not false on that meaning. But it is false on the meaning it has when it is true. So, what does it mean and is it true? I oppose the lambda suggestion. The annotation suggested is inadequate to do the fancy things that lambdas do: it cannot be used -- as it stand now -- to abstract complex sentences into predicates, since it does not adequate distinguish scopes. But I see no reason to correct this problem, since Lojban is already adequately (and then some) equipped to deal with abstracted sentences as arguments of higher order predicates (one main use of lambda) and has no need for the substitution-in-context procedure ( lambda conversion) which is the other major use -- in the metalanguage, not in the language in use. We can use our own abstractions instead, if we really have to show the relation of interest, but mainly we can just write out the resulting sentence. The correct thing to say about the second rabbit you see when you are using massifiers is not "another bit of Rabbit" or "another manifestation of Rabbit" but "Rabbit again". For good Trobrianders (assuming that they were not pulling Malinowski's leg -- a dangerous assumption I would say, based on my time among the Korwa) it is all the same guy. Take all the references in English or Lojban to individual rabbits or groups of them of any size and replace them all with the same single expression, "Rabbit," and you will get it about right. Actually, one use of lambda that might be of help here is pulling out what properties of individual rabbits applies to Rabbit, for, for example, if some particular rabbit never gets to Chicago but another one does, Rabbit has, of course, been to Chicago but also (not been to Chicago), which is not the denial of the first (Rabbit is real and therefore not self contradictory). *McCawley, James D., Everything that Linguists have Always Wanted to Know about Logic but were ashamed to ask, UChicago, 1981 (I think there is a revised edition) is a great place to read up on the logic that gets into linguistics: e.g., opaque contexts, lambda calculus. It is a bit quirky however (the stuff on opaque contexts goes off on a tangent that misses a major point) so it needs to be checked off against a logicians' view of linguistics. I recommend Logic, Language, and Meaning by L.T.F. Gamut, the name of massification of a set of Dutch logicians and linguists, especially vol 2., Intensional Logic and Logical Grammar. UChicago 1991. pc>|83