Received: from PSUVM.PSU.EDU (psuvm.psu.edu [128.118.56.2]) by locke.ccil.org (8.6.9/8.6.10) with SMTP id MAA03642 for ; Tue, 8 Aug 1995 12:51:13 -0400 Message-Id: <199508081651.MAA03642@locke.ccil.org> Received: from PSUVM.PSU.EDU by PSUVM.PSU.EDU (IBM VM SMTP V2R2) with BSMTP id 7631; Tue, 08 Aug 95 12:46:09 EDT Received: from PSUVM.PSU.EDU (NJE origin LISTSERV@PSUVM) by PSUVM.PSU.EDU (LMail V1.2a/1.8a) with BSMTP id 1214; Tue, 8 Aug 1995 12:45:50 -0400 Date: Tue, 8 Aug 1995 09:13:46 -0700 Reply-To: "John E. Clifford" Sender: Lojban list From: "John E. Clifford" Subject: quantifiers X-To: lojban list To: John Cowan Status: OR X-From-Space-Date: Tue Aug 8 12:51:18 1995 X-From-Space-Address: <@PSUVM.PSU.EDU:LOJBAN@CUVMB.BITNET> The usual suspects: > My point is that even "such that/ which is a" cannot cover > both of these connectives, that poi cannot be both conditional > and conjunctive. Why not? The conditional or the conjunction are a consequence of {ro} and {su'o}, not of {poi}. I am certainly not saying that you can replace word by word to go from one type of formula to the other. That is certainly not the case. pc: _da_ is a variable, so it ranges over certain things, deals distributively with them. These things are everything in the universe of discourse (or that exists, but that is another fight) unless we explicitly restrict to some other things. This restriction we do in Lojban with _poi_ followed by the predicate expression that defines the new range (_voi_ also works and, I expect, some other things as well). The distribution of _da_, restricted or not, is assumed to be disjunctive (su'o) unless otherwise indicated, in which case it becomes -- depending upon the quantifier used -- some more complicated kind of disjunctions and conjunctions, eventually tapering off (as these complexities tend to do) to a simple conjunctive distribution, (ro) where the remaining claim is asserted of each and every thing in the range of the variable. Through all of this, it is assumed that the range of the variable is not void, that something is being talked about, that there are some of the sort of things we are restricting to. None of this has anything to do with the rest of the claim in which the quantifier phrase (_da_ and any restriction and any explicit quantifier) is embedded. ro da poi broda cu brode then is (in theory) a conjunction of sentences ... cu brode, where the gap is filled in each conjunct by the name of a different broda and all the brodas turn up eventually. Similarly, ro da broda nagi'a brode is a conjunction of a bunch of sentences ... broda nagi'a brode, where the gap is filled each time by the name of something being talked about and eventually everything turns up in some sentence. Except when we are only talking about brodas, the second will be a much longer sentence (it is already more complex, since it has a compound predicate -- and thus is liable to expansion to a compound sentence -- while the first is simple). ro broda cu brode (i.e., ro lo broda ...) achieves the same result as the first sentence by a slightly different route (even without bringing in sets) as the present system stands. (As I write this, I do see a nice wedge here. It is the range of a variable that needs to be non-empty, not _ro_ per se. So, we could allow lo ro broda to refer to an empty set, since no variable is involved. Of course, the implicit external quantifier could no longer be _su'o_, I suppose -- or anything but ro, in fact. And the lo broda-da poi broda connection would be severed. Hmmmm!) The point is that in fact poi nor ro/su'o have nothing to do with -- and are prior to -- the both-and/ if-then features the matrix of the sentence. There is nothing even odd about ro da broda gi'e brode nor su'o da poi broda, cu brode nagi'a brodi (or, for that matter, su'o da poi broda nagi'a brode cu brodi). You really can come pretty close word-by-word here (well , sumtis affect sumtis and predicates affect predicates and connectives affect connectives anyhow). xorxes: Let me try to write everything down, otherwise I'm totally lost. The Lojban expressions in question are the following: 1a ro broda cu brode 1b ro da poi broda cu brode 1c ro da broda nagi'a brode 2a su'o broda cu brode 2b su'o da poi broda cu brode 2c su'o da broda gi'e brode My position is that 1a, 1b and 1c mean all the same thing, and likewise 2a, 2b and 2c mean all the same thing. Since we have no disagreement about the meaning of 1c, I think you are saying that either one or both of 1a and 1b mean something different, namely: 1d su'o da broda ije ro da broda nagi'a brode I think that it is not worth it to complicate matters by giving 1a or 1b or both the meaning 1d, and I don't see a problem with that position. We can of course give that meaning to one or both of 1a and 1b, but that only makes manipulating formulas more complicated, and I don't see the advantage. The existential import can always be recovered anyway using an explicit inner quantifier {ro lo su'o broda}. pc: Actually, I would not really take 1a and 1b to mean the same as 1d although they turn out to be true on the same occasions (assuming, to avoid much more muddling matters, that all the brodas are in the domain of discourse or that restriction is to a subdomain). They get to the same situations by very different routes, just as all of the 2s get to the same situations, but by very different routes. That is, 1a (left in its reading), 1b and 1d are equivalent but not synonymous. Note that 1b -- in many ways the most basic form -- does not have access to an alternate device for existential import (there is nowhere to put the su'o). xorxes: (BTW, conversationally, usually I implies O and O implies I, but we don't force that one on the quantifiers. Why should we force the others?) pc: Oddly, that implication has been held to be Gricean by just about everyone who has noticed it (including Aristotle, who did not call it Gricean, of course). But, in fact, various studies have shown that it really does not exist for most people most of the time (cf. the alleged exclusive "or"). The same studies tend to confirm the existential import phenomenon. sos: > O: Some S is not P (xu'o?) Yes, it would be nice to have such {xu'o}. If the default for the complement of {da'a} was "at least 1", rather than 1, I think that would be it. pc: I don't recognize da'a, but the complement of xu'o would not be "at least one." As noted it is (as far as I am concerned) "every". xu'o broda cu brode means something like [if]da broda [then] de broda [and not] brode (I'll catch on to this -- the at least fourth -- set of connectives eventually) xorxes: if {ro} and {su'o} are to be duals there has to be no existential import, and I think that relationship between them is important. I don't think A should imply I, nor E O. pc: Why is duality so important but existential import not? Duality is, after all, only a pleasant technical trick in some logic systems, existential import is a psychologically significant claim about the world. And, given the pains taken in Lojban to get rid of negation problems, even the technical trick is relatively unused. I am not even sure what to do with the duality of ro and su'o in Lojban, since naku ro da naku broda seems a pretty implausible thing to want to say. And it IS equivalent to suo da broda anyhow-- other cases are more complex. xorxes: I guess it's just a matter of aesthetics. To me these two should be exactly equivalent: re da poi nanmu cu pencu re de poi gerku re da poi nanmu ku re de poi gerku zo'u: da pencu de And the same should hold for: re nanmu cu pencu re gerku re nanmu re gerku zo'u: ny pencu gy I guess you could define them as being different, but I would find it aesthetically wrong. pc: I don't see the aesthetic point. The assumption is that a change in an expression signals some change. And the case I was discussing involved also re da poi nanmu re da poi gerku cu pencu (which I have to admit does seem to me to mean the same -- except for emphasis, perhaps -- as the first case). In this case certainly the change is not a superficial one (as it is in the parenthetically mentioned case) but a profound one that alters the whole underlying structure of the sentence, syntactically and logically. Syntactically (one story anyhow, others are parallel) the sentence shifts from one with a predicate (pencu) head to one with a quantification head. Logically, the scopes of the quantifiers are changed (at least -- I think rather more is involved). In any case, simplicity -- an aesthetic virtue -- and coherence -- another -- would suggest that such a change meant something. And it does. The question is only whether it is enough to carry the freight I claim for it. xorxes: > As for the re prenu e re >gerku form, that has to > expand into a conjunction of two sentences, each with a single sumti in > the prenex. I don't see why, since they are not filling the same argument place. Anyway, it would be just a consistent convention. Another possibility would be using {jo'u}, which doesn't seem to have any use. pc: jo'u may work, though it seems a little odd (mass? set?, I forget which), but e form already has a consistent convention F x e y G => FxG ije FyG. Since they are both in the prenex position, they are filling exactly the same place (have to be to be connected by e), the fact that they are anaphorized in different places doesn't count -- except for making the expansion mean something different from what the original was intended to mean. xorxes: > My version does technically put one > in the scope of > the other, but since it is indifferent which is in the scope of which > (the two are > equivalent), this does not force the separate > instantiations It is indifferent if you define it like that, otherwise it wouldn't be : I would read it as "there are exactly two men for which there are exactly two dogs such that...", i.e. for each of the men. Of course, you can also define it to have equal scope and read it as "there are exactly two men and there are exactly two dogs such that..., but I thought we had agreed that this was not the most useful way of doing it. (I don't know what are Skolem functions.) pc: I do not see why you want to read the "for which" in there, since it is not in there. I do not have to define it as having equal scope, since I can prove that the two scope-readings are equipollent. So far as I can recall, the only agreement that has actually been expessed is that the re nanmu cu pencu re gerku version could involve up to four dogs, two for each man. The present task is to find a way to say some of the other things, particularly (in this case) the two dogs total version (the others take other quantifier orders or, as you say -- so this is another agreement -- get involved in masses). Skolem functions (Thoralf, can't find his dates but this stuff is from 191x) are a technical trick to replace each particular quantifier (su'o) with a function that takes as arguments all the universally bound variables within whose scope the particular quantifier lay. The device could be generalized to a function which took as arguments all the terms on which its value depended: which might not be all the universal quantifiers but might also include additional floating terms: other particulars (i .e., other Skolem functions) and even constants. The crucial point for this discussion is that it makes the dependence of the value of a term on other terms explicit. pc>|83