Return-Path: LOJBAN%CUVMB.BITNET@vms.dc.LSOFT.COM Received: from SEGATE.SUNET.SE (segate.sunet.se [192.36.125.6]) by xiron.pc.helsinki.fi (8.7.1/8.7.1) with ESMTP id EAA06156 for ; Sun, 28 Jan 1996 04:15:02 +0200 Message-Id: <199601280215.EAA06156@xiron.pc.helsinki.fi> Received: from listmail.sunet.se by SEGATE.SUNET.SE (LSMTP for OpenVMS v1.0a) with SMTP id 472B8AE6 ; Sun, 28 Jan 1996 3:15:02 +0100 Date: Sat, 27 Jan 1996 18:05:24 -0800 Reply-To: "John E. Clifford" Sender: Lojban list From: "John E. Clifford" Subject: tech:logic matters X-To: lojban list To: Veijo Vilva Content-Length: 9471 Lines: 192 Carter (still doing business at the old stand): St. Anselm's Ontological Proof of the Existence of God is a famous example of the existential import of "all". pc: An interesting idea that, but I can't think of any reason to believe it, since I could not find a quantifier in it anywhere that was not demonstrably instantiated. No use of import, in a word (or four). Carter: If I understand correctly the comments you made about history of logic, you are a rock solid Aristotlean whereas And & I cleave to the Stoic school. Or maybe the Frege school. pc: Well, the Stoics don't come in, since they are the propositional logic people as Aristotle is the quantifier guy. Frege (and some predecessors) figured out how to use bits of propositional logic to do bits of the quantifier work as well. Carter: Anyway, I found it a very liberating experience to discover that "all" doesn't have existential import. Whereas as seen by you, that's just wrong -- at your mother's knee you learned that "all" has existential import, and And & I are simply wrong. pc: We have to do some distinguishing here, since another note suggests we have all gotten a mass of things mixed together. The import status of the English word "all," as used in ordinary langauge is rather unclear, possibly to the level of idiolectic variation (you say nay, I say yea). The question was about the *logical* word "all", as represented by the universal quantifier (however that, in its turn, may be represented). That one's status I learned not at my mother's knee but at Church (Alonzo), and it clearly has existential import, AxFx entails ExFx, even in Frege. Part of the claim of Lo??an being a logical language is that its universal quantifier (_ro_ in the current version) is the logical one. And so it has existential import. This is, of course, the quantifier in its logical form, prenex and binding a variable. This form is derived, historically and now metalinguistically, from logical form closer to natural language forms: a quantified noun phrase + singular verb phrase, "All S is P," in which, as Geach used to grumble, the "all" should properly have been "every," a quantifier about whose import there is no serious doubt (it has it). The derivation (running mainly through the 19th century) took the form of reducing the subject term to a vacuity, "thing" roughly, and recreating the subject in various ways in a complex predicate, finally, with "all," as the antecedent of a material conditional. Because of the rules about material conditionals -- true whenver the antecedent is false, these new versions of "All S is P," i.e., Ax:Sx => Px, were true when there were no S's, while the original version was false. Originally, Lo??an had only the strict modern form for universal (and other quantified) claims: quantifier, variable, form containing variable (conditional in the case of universals). But for all sorts of practical reasons, this situation changed rapidly to one where quantifiers were used -- with the same meaning as before -- to modify first existing sumti and eventually even bridi (similar to the basic English pattern). At some point, the conflict between these new Lo??an forms and the very similar English forms -- as well as the also similar old logical forms -- led to the introduction of a way of making explicit the form with existential import of the subject (not just the generic existential import of the quantifier), _ro da poi..._. This form was picked partly because it was about all that was available, partly because it was more complex and the expectation was that the importing form would not be so common. It did give, of course, another target than _ro da ganai da broda gi ..._ to claim as underlying _ro broda cu..._ and _ro lo broda cu ..._ but these were -- until Cowan's recent move (for other reasons) -- left as abbreviating only the usual modern form. Note, however, that throughout all of this the universal quantifier as such has continued to have existential import for its subject, the difference being only what its subject is (things or a mentioned sort of things). i,n: > > They are the quantifiers of natural language ... You keep insisting on this, but McCawley doesn't appear to think that it's quite so clear cut. ... while 6.3.4b would probably be interpreted as including members who incurred no bills among those to whom the 10 percent discount is offered: ... 6.3.4 b. Any member who paid all his bills by the fifteenth of the month was entitled to a 10 percent discount on their publications. pc: See earlier. Notice here that the question is not about "all" but "any," which notoriously does not have existential import (see Vendler's article in the Dictionary of Philosophy or the paper it is based on). Further, the point here was about what could be handled by restricted quantifiers (second order predicates of a certain sort) and "any" clearly fits in that category (subject term is included in predicate term, usual sense of "included"). i,n > whatever is the denial of _ro_ (?_ronai_? _nairo_? something else > altogether?). {naku ro} or {da'a su'o} pc: Neither of these work very well, given everybody's habit of pushing negations around, in the first case, and the existential import in the second. When the restricted quantifiers were introduced, the quantifier set was expanded to contain the fourth corner to the traditional square -- contradictory to _ro_, subaltern to _no_ and subcontrary to _su'o_ -- but I have lost all track of the form used. i,n: The other thing that needs to be worked out is how the existential-universal interacts with (bridi) negation. You may consider it to be a trivial exercise for the reader, but it's a significant part of the negation paper, and virtually part of the definition of what {na} and {naku} mean. pc: Why we had four quantifiers in the final set: negations carried to the diagonally opposite quantifier with all else unchanged. i,n: Given that we want to be able to express both "one and all" (universal with existential import) and "any and all" (universal which may be vacuous) in simple forms such as the above, we need a quantifier for each. I previously offered you something like {ro su'o} as an existential- universal to contrast with plain {ro} as a possibly-vacuous universal, but you weren't impressed. You did not however offer me a possibly-vacuous universal in return, except as a circumlocution, which the above seems to indicate you agree is undesirable. I am therefore forced to propose my own, {ro su'o no}, which is not particularly pretty, but I can always hope that usage will eventually establish that a naked {ro} is at least ambiguous between the two possibilities, as it is in English, and preferably that {ro su'o no} is the default interpretation, at least barring pragmatic indications to the contrary. (I have no particular objections to particular constructions such as {ro lo broda} carrying existential import, providing it can be explained in such a way that this is not part of the meaning of {ro}, but arises from the context as a whole, for instance by a default {su'o} inner quantifier. If it could also be explained using your definitions, and still end up with the same meaning, then we might both be satisfied, but I won't hold my breath. In any case, I think we need some explicit quantifiers, such as discussed above, up our sleeves, to override whatever implications might arise from the context.) pc: We have all of these things -- in various degrees of complexity and with various theories about what expression means what -- already. The only thing we do not have is a universal affirmative quantifier that does not have inherent existential import. Since I cannot quite imagine why anyone would want to talk about a universe which was totally empty (or, indeed, what one could say about it), this lack seems far too minor to be worth hassling about. Even _ro su'o no_ (which does not make much sense to me, as indeed does not _ro su'o_) seem way too short an expression for the purpose, which has not yet turned up in any text. &: So how do you make sense of {no lo ro broda}? And must {lo no broda e lo ro broda cu brode} be false? pc: {no lo ro broda} "none of the broda," i.e., there are some but none of them fit whateve goes on thereafter. {lo no broda e lo ro broda cu brode} is false because it simultaneously asserts that the class of broda has some members and that it does not (another reason, I think, for being sceptical about those internal quantifiers, but that is another issue). &: "Most" can be done as a predicate taking sets as arguments. (I recognize that you're being more orthodox than me here, but I'm too much of an outsider to understand why the orthodoxy is the orthodoxy.) pc: Hey, that is exactly what I just said quantifiers are in the general theory. That is, you recommend treating it just like the others (or the general theory recommends treating the others just like "most"). Colin: structures like re lo xirma and re lo ci xirma would appear to be anomolous pc: Not anomolous as such but just as representing quantifier expressions directly. Many of them turn out to be reducible to quantifier expressions but it takes a couple of steps. Of course, _re lo ci xirma_ also has that extra bit about how many xirma there are altogether and that is a different factor. pc>|83