[Date Prev][Date Next][Thread Prev][Thread Next][Date Index][Thread Index]
Link on (Intensional) Masses
Godehard Link. 1983. The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms:
A Lattice-theoretical Approach. In Baeuerle, R., C. Schwarze & A. von
Stechow (eds), Meaning, Use and the Interpretation of Language.
Berlin: de Gruyter. 303-23.
[Link does an extensionalist approach to substance: he has a, b, the
goo of a, the goo of a+b (his mu-operator below is the goo of all
x:P(x)), and the collective of a+b.]
Before I go on to present my own approach I want to say something
about what ter Meulen calls nominal mass terms. Typical examples are
stuff names like "gold" in sentences like "gold has the atomic number
79". But there is also the time-honoured sentence "water is
widespread" in which the term "water" has apparently a somewhat
different status. It seems to refer to the concrete "scattered
invidivual" that you just find everywhere, hence Quine's analysis in
terms of mereology. In this sense the sentence should be synonymous
with "the water (on earth) is widespread". Of the same type is the
use of "gold" in "America's gold is stored in Fort Knox." Here,
again, a concrete object is referred to by "America's gold", namely
the material fusion of all quantities of the US gold reserve. [In my
terms, the Substance of the Collective of the Individuals of Stuff].
So there can be no doubt that some notion of fusion is needed to
account for definite descriptions involving predicative mass terms
(the mu-operator defined below does just this.) Genuine stuff names,
however, are something else. Substances are abstract entities and
cannot be defined in terms of their concrete manifestations. The
question, then, is of what kind the connections are that are
intuitively felt between substances and their quantities. Take
water, for instance. A quantity is water if it displays the internal
structure of water, that is H2O. But this relation is not a logical
one. Or else we might look for substance properties which carry over
to the quantities of the substance in question. Water is a liquid and
yet, all concrete water might be frozen. So we have to go to
dispositional properties, getting more and more involved into our
knowledge of the physical world... What I am getting at is that
*nominal mass terms do not seem to have a proper logic*. Be that as
it may, this issue is completely independent of the lattice structure
that governs the behaviour of predicative mass terms and plural
expressions; it is only this structure that I want to address myself
to in the present paper.
[... So Link only talks about bits of stuff, in the end: extensional
quantities. In fact, he only ever has "goo of thing" not "goo on its
own", or even "some of the goo."
His footnote has me worried:]
Contributions to the problem of substance names can be found in
Pelletier (1979) (in particular, Parsons (1979)), Bunt (1979), and
ter Meulen (1980, 1981). Let me comment on the latter work, which is
formulated in a Montague framework. The few remarks I made here will
make it evident that I fully agree with ter Meulen in that nominal
mass nouns cannot be *reduced* to predicative mass nouns. But for
this very reason I fail to see any cogent argument for the kind of
denotation ter Meulen wants to assign to these terms at a given
reference point (i.e. intension functions denoting in each world the
set of concrete quantities of the substance in quesion.) As it turns
out, the arguments she puts forth in ter Meulen (1981) really lend
support only to the first, the critical point (viz. that reduction is
impossible.) But what she then goes on to call a nominal mass noun's
"extensional reference to an intensional object" (viz. the intension
function referred to above) seems to me both syntactically and
semantically misguided. For the inevitable doubling of syntactic
rules is certainly unwelcome, to begin with. But what is more, those
intension functions, even when lifted to still another intensional
level as ter Meulen wants to have it, are simply not well motivated
as substance name denotations. The statement, for instance, that two
fictional substaces can be differentiated (op. cit., p. 438) is not
compatible with the principle of rigid designation introduced earlier
(op. cit., p. 424). More generally, there are no rules that could
justify intuitively valid inferences from contexts involving nominal
mass nouns to contexts with their corresponding predicative terms ---
it is my view, anyway, that such inferences are not based on pure
logic alone. conclude from this that the problem of nominal mass
nouns is best approached in a spirit of logical abstinence. Nominal
mass nouns denote abstract entities, to be sure, and as such they are
the names of individuals just like "John", "Munich", and the rest.
Beyond this minimal account things become notoriously vague.
[I swear to God I did not read this footnote before I said "half the
water is a Kind." I *think* he's saying "Water is a Kind, and as such
does not admit any extensional definition." In particular, looking
for concrete bits of water in possible worlds isn't going to cut it:
the reference is rather more generic than that.
I think he's right.
I think this is our solution. In which case, it's no coincidence that
both And's Substance-Not-Just-Bits-of-Substance and my current Kind
are quantified by tu'o. They *are* the same thing.]
--
**** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** ****
* Dr Nick Nicholas, French & Italian Studies nickn@unimelb.edu.au *
University of Melbourne, Australia http://www.opoudjis.net
* "Eschewing obfuscatory verbosity of locutional rendering, the *
circumscriptional appelations are excised." --- W. Mann & S. Thompson,
* _Rhetorical Structure Theory: A Theory of Text Organisation_, 1987. *
**** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** ****