[Date Prev][Date Next][Thread Prev][Thread Next][Date Index][Thread Index]

lojbabbitry a (ce'u)



In a message dated 9/10/2001 6:25:29 PM Central Daylight Time,
lojbab@lojban.org writes:




A point I have been trying to stress whenever I say "let usage
decide".  Usage will not have decided while there are still only ahandful
of people competent enough at the easy stuff that they are willing to essay
using the more complex or abstract ones.  And I daresay there are a lot of
people who might USE the language more if they could successfully pull
themselves away from the endless arguments ABOUT the language.





<Membership in a selma'o may imply NOTHING about its semantics.  Membership
in NU means only that it serves as the head of a phrase that includes a
bridi and is terminated by a possibly elidable kei.>

Which gives some prima facie clues about its semantics, unless the included
bridi is just window dressing (not a possibility I considered until the{me
mi mo'e moi} fiasco).

<How about one where it stands by itself, developing its own meaning? A si'o
abstraction "means" NOTHING other than that which fills the x1 of sidbo, a
ka abstraction is an x2 of ckaji and a few other predicates, a ni
abstraction is an x1 of klani, a sedu'u is an x2 of cusku.  Deciding what
place structures applied to these abstractions did some constraining ofthe
meanings, but relatively little.  Arguing whether a si'o is a kind ofka is
a philosophical argument, of the sort that can never be settled, because it
hinges on whether one is willing to consider an idea to be a characteristic
of something (i.e., is the x1 of sidbo an x2 of ckaji?)  We are NOT going
to agree, and the argument is therefore fruitless.>

Well, it is not obvious that we will never agree, since it is not obvious
that the argument is philosophic rather than linguistic, in which practical
features, for example, might play a role.  More importantly, it israrely the
case that the conclusion is the only fruit of discussion -- a better
understanding of what is involved in a particular abstraction or in
abstractions generally may arise, as well as some infrmation about all those
places that these abstractions fill and the selbri where they fill them.  
Seems at least as valuable as another dozen banal sentences in safe
constructions.

<Saying more or less what I said.  Equating the places of two different
predicates in some absolute manner serves as a metaphysical restrictionon
how we look at the universe.  Lojban tries to avoid such metaphysical
constraints.  Semantic conventions are thus to some extent bad thingsif
they are rationalized, because the rationalization will always be in view
of some particular metaphysical outlook.>

The worst kind of pseudo-whorfian claptrap.  The argument it claims to be in
accord with was a refutation of the claim that {si'o} and {ka} were alike, in
support of the claim that {si'o} and {nu} are alike, so not at all what
Lojbab said in the first place and  he said nothing like the gist of the
argument in the second.  That aside, some notion of how the semantics of
various phrases works is not at all metaphysically constraining, since --
once we know how things goes -- we can account for them equally well ina
variety of ways metaphysically.  To be sure, a nice picture helps for a while
in formulating a theory, but the picture is not the theory.  And the theory
is not metaphysical.

<Nora and I, with less than full reading of all these intertwining threads
of abstractors seem to glorkjunkie that si'o is supposed to be the
archetype that you are talking about above.  If this is the case thenlo'e
is a manifestation of that archetype (and not the archetype itself (which
manifestation may or may not actually exist in the real world)).  We
discuss ideas, and not manifestations of those ideas.

More specifically, while lo pavyseljirna may not exist, lo'e pavyseljirna
is something that people draw pictures and write books about as if such
things did exist, and those things are distinct from the ideas/ideals we
have of them: the idea of a unicorn is not going to carry a fair maiden,
the manifestation of that idea would do so.

Now it might still be the case that we should use something like lo'e tanxe in
mi sisku lo'e tanxe, because we probably aren't seeking properties, but
manifestations that have the property.   This is not quite what Jorge had
in mind since it does not equate ka and lo'e, but it might clarify/correct
what is intended when we talk about seeking a property (which if people
recall was introduced to keep people from searching for noda when they were
searching for lo pavyseljirna which does not exist).>

Thus avoiding all metaphysics!  Ideas, ideals, archetypes, manifestations of
archetypes, real things, properties... An ontology to make Plato weep -- and
Aristotle too fror the opposite reason.  I especially like being able to
paint a picture of a manifestation of an archetype -- an presumably not
ending with a blank canvas.  
Now, what does all this mean in terms of linguistic usage?  Well, we do have
the note that maybe we seek manifestations of archetypes rather than
properties, i.e. lo'e broda rather than ka ce'u broda (we can at least keep
up with the latest decision of usage).  But of course we rarely do; any old
unicorn will do, even if it far from a manifestation of the archetype
(unless, of course, every unicorn is a manifestation of the archetype, in
which case we are probably back at the problem that there are no unicorns,
again)

<My own preferred but totally unofficial rule for zo'e
>is that it is a variable bound by an existential quantifier with
>maximally narrow scope, so zo'e are bound within the abstraction,
>and hence {ro ka broda cu pa mei}. However, if there is no specific
>rule for the binding/reference-fixing of zo'e (and if its reference
>can be fixed arbitrarily within the abstraction, i.e so that it can't
>be exported to prenex of main bridi), then {na ku ro ka broda cu pa
>mei}, because there'd be as many {ka broda} as there are construalsof
>the zo'e within it. IMO that would be a Bad Thing, because all
>abstractions would become intolerably vague, except to glorkjunkies.

Nora opines that apparently then you may be stuck with the glorkjunkie
version, because when we use ka anaphorically, we appear to get the result
you dislike

Thus if we are discussing
lo ka ce'u lebna loi titla loi cifnu
we might later anaphorically refer to
le ka lebna
where we clearly may want the zo'es to be carried over indefinitely.

on the other hand it isn't always the case that we want the zo'es to carry
over.>

Anaphora is different from scoping problems: we need only a reminder to
recover the whole-- complete with it bound terms.

<At 06:04 PM 8/31/01 +0100, And Rosta wrote:
>{le si'o ce'u broda kei be mi} = my notion of Broda

That might be your notion of "le broda", just as

{le si'o broda ce'u kei be mi}

might be your notion of "le se broda"

But let us turn to some abstractions that people often label as Ideas, like
"Freedom" and "Peace".  I can't figure out whether the ce'u goes in those
or why you would want to use one.  Yet I have to claim/concede that ce'uless

le si'o zifre kei be mi

is not the same as ce'uless

le ka zifre

because the latter does not have "mi" in the place structure, nor is either
of these clearly the same as

le du'u zifre

though the latter two seem closer than the si'o is to either.>

Oh goody!  We need another kind of idea, Idea.  Actually, I think that this
is correct, since the properties we have so far and the ideas, too, tend to
be very extensional and we need the intensions as well -- at the risk of
being accused of metaphysics rather than Logic at this point.