[Date Prev][Date Next][Thread Prev][Thread Next][Date Index][Thread Index]
RE: kau: instantiation
cu'u la .and.
Nick:
I assume that {kau} always implies {djuno} or
something like that somewhere along the line,
We had assembled a testcase corpus of non-djuno-based 'indirect
questions'.
I'm very happy you did assemble these, because that's how the
relevance of this discussion gets proven. That said, are all of these
really that problematic? As you yourself admit, they needn't all take
{kau}. So:
What the last digit of my phone number is has changed.
Is this different from "the last digit of my phone number has
changed"? I don't see how right now.
What I eat depends on what's in the fridge.
i have a vague recollection that I saw this once, and that the
question "isn't this just a headless relative clause" has already
been raised. I think this one's got me: it's instantiation, and it's
not clearly related to cognition (whereas Jorge's counterexamples of
forgetting and deciding were.) So I can't immediately see how {djuno}
resolves this. {kau} is intuitively appealing here; I don't know yet
whether it's right. I'm fairly sure we can't cut the Gordian knot
here, though, and say {le se citka be mi....} This isn't a claim
about food, but about a particular instantiation of food fitting in a
predication.
John differs from Jane in how tall they are.
This is akin to "John exceeds Jane in how tall they are", which is
resolved as {la djan. zmadu la djein. leni ce'u galte}. The problem
then becomes, of course, what does {ni} mean; but we were going to
have to resolve this anyway.
But your second example is giving me pause. You may have trapped me.
Believe me, I'm looking forward to Karttunen's paper on questions.
****
A DEFENCE OF jboske and Formal semantics
I say this as much to convince myself as anyone else, because I find
these debates frustrating, confusing, and bewildering.
But I feel I have to say this more explicitly, because xod's praise
embarasses me a little. Just because egghead X says something holds
in the semantics of English, doesn't mean we in Lojban have to buy
into it. Remember, Carlson may have argued that all bare plurals in
English, whether generic ("Dogs eat meat") or individuals ("I saw
dogs"), are the same thing underlyingly; but Carlson's explaining
English, so he would say that. He's got something to prove, after all.
It also doesn't mean that the formal semanticists are on the right
track. Geoff Sampson wrote a sympathetic book review of CLL, as you
may know (I'm getting someone to type it up for me and will send it
to list, because people don't seem to know about it.) Well, Sampson
also wrote a book I glimpsed today, trashing formal semantics so
thoroughly, I was wondering what the hell I was doing being
interested in it. Sort of like xod on a good day. :-)
But. But when we work with Lojban, we find some logical notions
embedded in the language by its designers. They have a history and a
context; it makes sense to find out what they are, to see if we need
them and if they help in our understanding of What Lojban Shall Do.
(This is, obviously, an open question.)
And clearly, And, Jorge and pc know a lot about this background. (And
that the trade does have many an unresolved debate.) I don't. In
fact, when I realised I didn't, and that I was speaking about Lojban
semantics without knowing any formal semantics, I bowed out of
Lojban. (OK, there was the small matter of my PhD too, but I realised
I'd been talking crap, and I don't like talking crap.)
And yet this stuff is fun. When it stays clearcut, at least; before
too long, though, you don't know whether you're coming or going. As
we're all finding. It's fun on its own, even independent of Lojban; I
always did want to learn it anyway.
(I have to say, though, falsifiable syllogisms are a delightful
change to me, after several years of historical and literary
reasoning that's full of hedges and maybes and probablys. It sucks
following a train of thought for a couple of hours, only to realise
that it can't possibly work; but it's also heartening, because
disproof is instructive too.)
This doesn't mean Kartunnen holds the solution to all our {kau}
problems. He may well not, especially if he's got some set-based
Montague stuff that won't fit nicely into Lojban. But then again, he
might. And even if he doesn't, it'll help me understand you guys,
because you've obviously read it. (Nothing in Lojban tells you that
an answer is a set of predications; that's formal semantics talking.
And to my amusement, I see that Karttunnen says answers are a set of
preds in 1977, and then Groenendijk & Stokhof in 1989 say no, surely
answers must be individual constituents as well (just as xod did),
and do some type-shifting (think tu'a) to make the logic work.)
This doesn't mean G&S and xod are in cahoots, or that they'd even go
to the same clubs. But I do think it's illuminating to see how some
linguists tackle these issues, and how some lojbanists tackle the
same issues, and can we get anything useful out of the linguists.
(And the logicians and the philosophers; one of the things Sampson
trashed the formal semanticists about was that they were doing
philosophy without talking to the philosophers.) Because Kartunnen
wasn't necessarily right either. And since we're making all this
stuff up, there's no 'right' anyway; there's just 'more elegant',
'more learnable', and 'more consistent'.
--
**** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** ****
* Dr Nick Nicholas, French & Italian Studies nickn@unimelb.edu.au *
University of Melbourne, Australia http://www.opoudjis.net
* "Eschewing obfuscatory verbosity of locutional rendering, the *
circumscriptional appelations are excised." --- W. Mann & S. Thompson,
* _Rhetorical Structure Theory: A Theory of Text Organisation_, 1987. *
**** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** **** ****