[Date Prev][Date Next][Thread Prev][Thread Next][Date Index][Thread Index]

Toward a {ce'u} record



"A propositional function [roughly, property or relation] is an incomplete
object whose completion is a proposition" (Frege, loose trat).  So, every
{ka} insofar as it creates a propositional function, property or relation,
contains at least one hole and that is marked by {ce'u}.  Did it contain no
holes, it would be a complete object and, asuming the original type was
right, a proposition.  
I*think* everyone agrees thus far.
So, the disagreement is about whether the {ce'u} must always be written in
and, if not, where the implicit one is.
1) Every {ce'u} must be explicit.  .  Any slot not filled by an overt marker
is filled by {zo'e} or some such thing.  At least one slot must be filled by
{ce'u} (unless we collapse the distinction between {ka} and {du'u}, in which
case, {du'u} are the {ce'u}-less {ka} -- or conversely).  An easy rule and
ambiguity-proof, but possibly verbose.
2) Not so -- some {ce'u} may be implicit, so long as there is a rule for  
identifying the place(s).  The rule may now be somewhat more complex, but the
results will be less verbose (generally).
A) The implicit {ce'u} is always the first (x1) place.  This runs into
immediate conflict with the possibility (indeed, reality) of {ka} phrases in
which the first place is filled with a content sumti.  This is not
ungrammatical, so it needs an interpretation.
i) Assuming there are no explicit {ce'u} in the phrase, this is treated like
other {ce'u}-less {ka} -- reduced to {du'u}. With an explicit {ce'u}
elsewhere, it is taken as the propositional function defined by the explicit
places, with no implicit ones (it was on a permission, after all).
ii) The {ce'u} is always in the first place, even if something else is also
there.  The something else is
a) an exemplary argument to which the function applies to produce a true
proposition or a new propositional function (depending on whether there are
explicit {ce'u}), but the {ka} phrase refers to this an all other such
functions. This does not seem to really give the first-place phrase any role
that would justify it being there, unless it is to suggest a range of values
for {ce'u}, and that would better be done using explicit predicates.
b) as in a), but now the {ka} phrase indicates just the function with the
sumti in first place.  This reduces to i).
c) like a) in all respects except that the sumti in first place markes a
special relationship between its referent and the function, which is
different from (but may include) the application relationship a) assumes.  
{leka do xunre} may or may not mean that {do xunre} is true, but it indicates
a special relationship between you and leka ce'u xunre.  The nature of this
relationship is not specified anywhere that I can find, and so the whole does
not seem different from {ledo ka ce'u xunre} (to be on the safe side), which
is also unexplained, but in the same way.
B) The implicit {ce'u} is the first unfilled place in the bridi as written
(if none then {du'u}). This comes, in a way that A) does not, into conflict
with other Lojbanic habits, in particular, not filling uninteresting places,
dropping {zo'e}. Using it correctly requires noticing that the place
(assuming it is not the first, as it most often will be) is important, since
it gets a {ce'u} and then dropping that {ce'u}.  It thus is harder to use
than A when it does not have the same effect as A and so harder than A
altogether, and more likely to errors in what is said.
C) A) and B) save at most a couple of syllables, so could B be generalized
to, say, all the unfilled spaces up to the first explicit {zo'e}.  This is
actually simpler than B) since we only have to decide that something is
unimportant and put in a {zo'e}, not decide it is important and then leave
out a {ce'u} we were going to put in.  It also gives rather natural results,
e.g. {le ka prami} is the love relationship, not either the property of being
loved or of being a lover. It could be extended (but I doubt it is worth it)
by returning to {ce'u} after an explicit one after a {zo'e}.

The last example raises a general issue: each occurrence of {ce'u} is new,
independent of others in the context (like {ma} and unlike {ke'a}).  How,
then, do we force two occurrences to be the same, as we can do with the
lambda operator from which {ce'u} derives.  How, for example, do we talk
about self-love, leka prami with the two implicit {ce'u} identified.  Notice,
we can't do this with any identity predicate, since that just introduces two
more {ce'u}, unconnected with the earlier ones.  For this and general
reasons, I suggest that {ce'u}, like KOhA generally, be taken as having
implicit subscripts (starting with 0) assigned in left to right order.  So,
self -love is le ka ce'uxino prami ce'uxino, which might be shortened somehow
(to, for example, {le ka prami ce'uxino}) but probably shouldn't be.