[Date Prev][Date Next][Thread Prev][Thread Next][Date Index][Thread Index]
Re: [lojban] Toward a {ce'u} record
At 11:25 AM 8/19/01 -0400, pycyn@aol.com wrote:
"A propositional function [roughly, property or relation] is an incomplete
object whose completion is a proposition" (Frege, loose trat). So, every
{ka} insofar as it creates a propositional function, property or relation,
contains at least one hole and that is marked by {ce'u}. Did it contain no
holes, it would be a complete object and, asuming the original type was
right, a proposition.
I*think* everyone agrees thus far.
I think so, put this way. To me the archetypal ka has holes in ALL places
that are unfilled, including all plausible modal places. Others seem to
think that the archetype has one and only one hole which is filled by the
ce'u and indicates what the property is "about".
I will agree that most places where a ka abstraction is used in a sumti are
single-hole examples, but I don't want the assumption that this is always
the case to hold because I'm pretty sure that exceptions can and will occur.
So, the disagreement is about whether the {ce'u} must always be written in
and, if not, where the implicit one is.
You use singular ce'u here, begging my issue.
1) Every {ce'u} must be explicit. . Any slot not filled by an overt marker
is filled by {zo'e} or some such thing. At least one slot must be filled by
{ce'u} (unless we collapse the distinction between {ka} and {du'u}, in which
case, {du'u} are the {ce'u}-less {ka} -- or conversely). An easy rule and
ambiguity-proof, but possibly verbose.
2) Not so -- some {ce'u} may be implicit, so long as there is a rule for
identifying the place(s). The rule may now be somewhat more complex, but the
results will be less verbose (generally).
How about 3) Like most aspects of the language, features which are implicit
are optional with no guarantee of a "rule" that identifies the
preference. After all there is no "rule" for what tense applies in a
tenseless bridi, or what number applies in a non-quantified sumti. There
are *conventions* for some cases but for the most part these conventions
are understood to be less-than-binding over all usages.
Conventions, being non-binding, are best when they are descriptive of
normal use and not prescription that contradict normal usage from before
the convention.
A) The implicit {ce'u} is always the first (x1) place. This runs into
immediate conflict with the possibility (indeed, reality) of {ka} phrases in
which the first place is filled with a content sumti. This is not
ungrammatical, so it needs an interpretation.
i) Assuming there are no explicit {ce'u} in the phrase, this is treated like
other {ce'u}-less {ka} -- reduced to {du'u}. With an explicit {ce'u}
elsewhere, it is taken as the propositional function defined by the explicit
places, with no implicit ones (it was on a permission, after all).
ii) The {ce'u} is always in the first place, even if something else is also
there. The something else is
a) an exemplary argument to which the function applies to produce a true
proposition or a new propositional function (depending on whether there are
explicit {ce'u}), but the {ka} phrase refers to this an all other such
functions. This does not seem to really give the first-place phrase any role
that would justify it being there, unless it is to suggest a range of values
for {ce'u}, and that would better be done using explicit predicates.
b) as in a), but now the {ka} phrase indicates just the function with the
sumti in first place. This reduces to i).
c) like a) in all respects except that the sumti in first place markes a
special relationship between its referent and the function, which is
different from (but may include) the application relationship a) assumes.
{leka do xunre} may or may not mean that {do xunre} is true, but it indicates
a special relationship between you and leka ce'u xunre. The nature of this
relationship is not specified anywhere that I can find, and so the whole does
not seem different from {ledo ka ce'u xunre} (to be on the safe side), which
is also unexplained, but in the same way.
No. It is unexplained in a different way. leka do xunre specifically
associates do with filling the x1 of xunre; ledo ka ce'u xunre says
absolutely nothing about a relationship between do and x1 or with any other
specific or modal place in the xunre predicate.
B) The implicit {ce'u} is the first unfilled place in the bridi as written
(if none then {du'u}). This comes, in a way that A) does not, into conflict
with other Lojbanic habits, in particular, not filling uninteresting places,
dropping {zo'e}. Using it correctly requires noticing that the place
(assuming it is not the first, as it most often will be) is important, since
it gets a {ce'u} and then dropping that {ce'u}. It thus is harder to use
than A when it does not have the same effect as A and so harder than A
altogether, and more likely to errors in what is said.
You are failing to distinguish between "interesting" and "important". All
of the places of a predicate are "important" by definition or they would
not be part of the place structure, but some are not interesting because
common sense or context is sufficient to identify the value, or because,
while we recognize that there has to be a value, we really aren't will to
think about what it is.
ce'u needs to be stated explicitly when the listener isn't likely to figure
it out from context.
C) A) and B) save at most a couple of syllables, so could B be generalized
to, say, all the unfilled spaces up to the first explicit {zo'e}. This is
actually simpler than B) since we only have to decide that something is
unimportant and put in a {zo'e}, not decide it is important and then leave
out a {ce'u} we were going to put in. It also gives rather natural results,
e.g. {le ka prami} is the love relationship, not either the property of being
loved or of being a lover. It could be extended (but I doubt it is worth it)
by returning to {ce'u} after an explicit one after a {zo'e}.
The last example raises a general issue: each occurrence of {ce'u} is new,
independent of others in the context (like {ma} and unlike {ke'a}). How,
then, do we force two occurrences to be the same, as we can do with the
lambda operator from which {ce'u} derives. How, for example, do we talk
about self-love, leka prami with the two implicit {ce'u} identified. Notice,
we can't do this with any identity predicate, since that just introduces two
more {ce'u}, unconnected with the earlier ones. For this and general
reasons, I suggest that {ce'u}, like KOhA generally, be taken as having
implicit subscripts (starting with 0) assigned in left to right order. So,
self -love is le ka ce'uxino prami ce'uxino, which might be shortened somehow
(to, for example, {le ka prami ce'uxino}) but probably shouldn't be.
leka ce'u prami ri
--
lojbab lojbab@lojban.org
Bob LeChevalier, President, The Logical Language Group, Inc.
2904 Beau Lane, Fairfax VA 22031-1303 USA 703-385-0273
Artificial language Loglan/Lojban: http://www.lojban.org